Notes on:
Bernstein, B. (2000) Pedagogy, Symbolic
Control and Identity. Theory, research,
critique. Revised edition.
Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers.
Dave Harris
Chapter one Pedagogic Codes and Their Modalities
of Practice (3-24)
This model is intended to be universal and to
include pedagogic practices outside schools,
including say relations between architects and
planners. This produces a general model that
focuses on 'underlying rules shaping the social
construction of pedagogic discourse and its
various practices', rather than say aspects of
contemporary educational systems. This is to
stand between more general series [presumably
reproductive ones] to explain the relationship
between knowledge and consciousness.
Reproduction theories are too limited and cannot
provide sufficient description of pedagogic
agencies and the discourse and practices, because
they focus on education as a carrier of external
power, while the actual structure which Carries
the power is less relevant. However the
logic and the structure of pedagogic discourse
needs to be examined. There is no need to see
education as a pathology or for social class to
become dominant in this examination. We're
after are 'the inner logic of pedagogic
discourse',the rules of construction, circulation,
contextualization and change, specifically:
How does the dominant distribution of power and
control generate and legitimize 'dominating and
dominated principles of communication'? How
does this distribution of principles 'regulate
relations within and between social groups'?
How do these principles distribute 'forms of
pedagogic consciousness'? (4).
Power can be distinguished from control although
they are 'embedded in each other' (5)
empirically. Power relations produce
boundaries between different categories which
might be groups discourse or agents. Power
produces 'dislocations … punctuations in social
space', the relations between categories, the
legitimate order between them. Control
however 'establishes legitimate forms of
communication appropriate to the different
categories', within the categories, or socializing
individuals and offering a potential for both
reproduction and change. Pedagogic discourse
features different categories, pedagogic practices
different forms of control, and together they
offer 'forms of pedagogic communications'.
However, a special terminology is required to show
how macro relations and micro interactions are
related, and this terminology should also operate
with general principles, generate specific
descriptions, and produce a range of modalities of
discourse and practice, including some which do
not currently exist.
Classification is the concept used to describe the
relationship between categories, but it does not
refer to some underlying defining attribute [I
think it must in practice], but rather refers to
relations between categories. These
relations need not be discursive ones, but
describe, for example 'the division of labour'(6)
[hints at some organic unity or
solidarity?]. School subjects have their own
boundaries and identity, but this is not justified
by some external discourse. Categories only
exist in relation to others and they can define
themselves against others [politically?].
However, we can see these as 'other categories in
the set' [so what defines the set?]. We can
see the exercise of power in the gap between
categories [so more confusion here because it's
categories of discourse which apparently maintain
'the principles of their social division of
labour']. Barriers can be broken down and
categories can lose their identities, so the
'insulation' has to be maintained, or at least its
principle does. What preserves insulation is
power and power relations [we seem to have come
full circle here].
There are strong and weak classifications
different degrees of insulation between
categories. With strong classification 'each
category has its unique identity, its unique
voice, its own specialized roles of internal
relations'(7) [so it is some kind of ideal or
formal possibility?], but classifications 'always
carry power relations'[power is something external
again]. These power relations are arbitrary,
but are 'hidden by the principle of the
classification' which comes to take on a reality
of its own connected to the integrity and
coherence of the individual. All the
contradictions and dilemmas have to be suppressed,
and this also functions as 'a system of psychic
defences', although these are 'rarely wholly
effective'.
As examples of classifications, we can compare the
medieval university with the modern one, as
examples of stronger and weakening
classifications. [Description of the
medieval university follows, with strong internal
divisions between mental and manual practice,
further reflected in the relationship between the
rhetorical and logical trivium and a more
applied quadrivium. These feature
different languages, roughly linguistic and
mathematical. God integrates the two,
permitting an excepted order of precedence or
'regulated discourse' to be constructed in the
trivium and then later applied. We can also
see this as constructing inner consciousness
before going on to consider the structure of the
outer. This reflected a division inside
Christianity itself - so it reflects this division
in pedagogy? It also forms the
characteristic European notion of consciousness as
a relation between inner and outer - the pedagogy
does or Christianity does? The church
provides the underlying power to maintain strong
classifications. In the modern university,
European knowledge is restructured, however and
singular discourses are grouped together in
regions. Apparently, modern subjects can be
seen as singular discourses because they have
unique names [!] and have 'very few external
references other than in terms of
themselves'. However, they became
regionalised following recontextualization, and
this regionalization was based on 'a
recontextualizing principle', although we don't
seem to be told what it is --doubtless a reworking
of one of the descriptions above. However,
these movements to different forms of
classification provide 'spaces for ideology to
play'(9), which is not defined either. New
forms of competition for resources and
indifference broke out within and between
regions. Overall, what an entirely unhelpful
example!]
Looking at institutions, we can see strong and
weak classifications in schools or
universities. For example, school
departments 'represent discourses', and they can
be strongly classified. It is common [later
I think this becomes 'essential'] to accompany
this with strong classification between the
institution and the outside as well. Strong
classifications therefore produce a hierarchy of
knowledge between common sense and school
knowledge [must do, in the interests of formal
coherence?] . Staff are also closely
identified with departments and this is a symbolic
allegiance, 'the sacred reason' (10), although
'the main reason' is that promotion follows from
departmental activity. The reproduction of
pedagogic discourse itself is not collective,
since the staff are weakly related and
specialized. 'Thus, the contents are not
open to public discussion and challenge' [by
teachers, that is]. The diagram (on page 10) also
resembles a temple, a symbolic representation 'of
the origin of the discourse' in Greek philosophy
and the church [all this is based on the way he
has drawn the diagram of course]. Discourses
are collected in, er, a collection code.
In weakly classified schools, boundaries are
permeable, but this also makes the institution
vulnerable to 'communications from the
outside'. Staff must be members of a strong
social network to integrate the differences, and
their relations 'cohere around knowledge itself'
[the whole thing is riddled with idealism].
This also provides an alternative power base
against the hierarchy.
Strong classifications of discourse also produced
temporal dislocations, 'although it is not
logically necessary' (11), since strongly
classified knowledge empirically produces a
progression from local knowledge through the usual
steps of simple operations to general
principles. If children drop out 'they are
likely to be positioned in a factual world tied to
simple operations, when knowledge is
impermeable. The successful have access to
the general principle'. [We only ever learn
general principles through acquiring school
knowledge -- now enter Rancière].
Some particularly successful people go on to
create the discourse itself and realise its
fundamental incoherence.
The whole discussion shows two rules. First,
where there are strong classifications, things
must be kept apart [a definitional rule again, a
rule stemming from his model], and vice
versa. We should go on to ask about whose
interest is behind these options [although I don't
think he ever does -he leaves us to imply that
some dreadful hierarchy is at work]
Classifications construct social spaces, as
translations of power relations, with the affects
of creating social divisions of labour, identities
and voices. The arbitrary nature of power
relations are disguised by the classifications and
various psychic systems of defence when they
appear necessary. Pedagogic practice itself
and how it forms consciousness requires a notion
of control to regulate and legitimise
communication. Framing affects such control,
in any pedagogic relationship. Framing helps
people acquire 'the legitimate message' (12) and
also establishes voice, although the two 'can vary
independently', since different modalities can
establish the same voice, while more than one
message can carry the voice [so what else affects
voice?]. Framing helps the discourse to be
realised, meanings are to be put together and in
what forms, people related in a given
context. Control was exercised over the
selection of the communication, its sequencing and
pacing, the criteria and 'the control over the
social base' (13). Framing can be strong and
weak, although the loss of control to the acquirer
in weak framing can be only 'apparent'.
Difference strengths of framing can affect the
different aspects of control above.
There are two systems of rules, those of social
order and those of discursive order [rules here
are not specific ones as in the above example, but
abstract necessities, functional prerequisites].
The first one relates to expectations of acquirers
and can be a source of labeling - 'which labels
are selected is a function of the framing'[?] [A
strange bit here, apparently strong framing seems
to be associated with positive labels, but weak
framing means more problems for the
acquirer]. With discursive order, we are
talking about selection, sequence, placing and
criteria. Framing can be represented in a
little equation, page 13, where instructional
discourse appear as above the line and regulated
discourse below it, this apparently shows that
'instructional discourse is always embedded in the
regulative discourse, and the regulative discourse
is the dominant discourse [empirically or
logically?]
Elements of the discourse can be framed with
varying strengths, and so can regulative and
instructional discourses. They do not
'always move in a complementary relation to each
other. But where there is a weak framing
over the instructional discourse, there must be
weak framing over the regulative discourse'.
In general, if framing is strong, we have a
visible pedagogic practice with explicit rules,
and where it is weak we have an invisible
pedagogic practice [the invisible practice is a
bit like the hidden curriculum and pedagogy, where
it all goes on implicitly, and the example cited
elsewhere is the progressive primary school where
the whole set of social relations teaches
something]. Now to 'write pedagogic
codes'(14) [a pompous way of saying supply more
detail].
Classification and framing can be strong or weak
and combined producing a range of modalities
[well, four, surely?]. Now we find that
classification relates both externally and
internally, to external relations and also to
internal classifications like those 'of dress, of
posture, of position', and spaces and objects can
also be strongly specialised or classified.
The same goes for framing. The external
value relates to communications outside that
pedagogic practice which affect it [the example is
whether or not you pay the doctor, which will
affect the sorts of legitimate communication you
can have with them. Your identity externally
can be strong or weak]. Here, 'social class
may play a crucial role', and external dimensions
of school framing can 'make it difficult for
children of marginalised classes to recognise
themselves in the school'. So we have more
complications on the four basic possibilities,
since classification and framing are not only
strong or weak, but internal or external [I still
think this only gives 16 possibles]. There
is one of Bernstein's nice little equations to
show the elaborated orientation on page 15 - it
has strong classification and framing [I
think. Actually the diagram seems to show
all the possibilities again, but in that case the
elaborated orientation would be no different from
the restricted one in the abstract, but only when
we actually entered values].
Classification and framing produce rules of the
pedagogic code, 'that is, of its practice, but not
of the discourse'. The changing values of
classifications and framing produce different
organisational practices, discursive practices,
transmission practices, psychic defences, concepts
of the teacher, concepts of the pupils, concepts
of knowledge itself and expected pedagogic
consciousness. There is always pressure to
weaken framing, because pedagogic practices are
always an arena for struggle over symbolic
control. Framing is the most likely source
of change in the classification. The
connection between classification and power never
completely removes 'contradictions, cleavages and
dilemmas', at social and individual levels.
One problem with the notion of cultural
reproduction is that these possibilities ['rules'
again] are usually never specified. [well --not
formally identified in these terms nor seen as
'rules' ? But internal and external change factors
are clearly listed in say Homo Academicus]
We can suggest some possibilities. If there
are changes from strong to weak, either with
framing or classification, we can always ask
'which group was responsible for initiating the
change?', dominated or dominating. If values
are weakening, which one still remains
strong? [And how do we answer these
questions?]
Pedagogic practice therefore has its own internal
logic [based on the abstract possible
combinations] , and classification and framing
produces different modalities, especially of
'official elaborated codes'(16) [so are there
unofficial ones?]. These can shape the
consciousness of the acquirer, but we need to
explore this and go beyond transmission.
Such consciousness of acquirer and transmitter can
show 'biasing', although we are not going to refer
to ideology, because the system constructs
ideology. It is 'a way of making
relations. It is not a content but a way in
which relationships are made and realized'[weird
and confusing -- could be that ideology is or is
embedded in practices as in Althusser?]
A nice new diagram appears on page 16 to put
together all the concepts developed and show their
[formal] dynamics. These will demonstrate
'the model of acquisition within any pedagogic
context'. First there is a connection
between classification and 'recognition
rules... at the level of the acquirer'
(17). As classification strength changes, so
individuals are able to 'recognise the speciality
of the context that they are in'[strong
classifications mean you're in a special
educational situation]. Classification shows
that one context differs from another, and some
contexts are distinct and require a particular
orientation for communication. In university
seminars, the members 'share a common recognition
rule' whatever their disciplinary background, and
this helps them read the context and contribute
appropriately. It's not always easy for him
to infer a discursive context for the particular
questions, however, and in this case the weakly
classified context can create ambiguity [so is
this saying that students do recognise what's
going on better than lecturers do? Or that
seminars can be both recognized and not very well
recognized? Or that recognition affects
behaviour, but lack of recognition affects
content?].
Apparently, strong classification produces strong
recognition rules and power relations and this
helps to produce legitimate communication.
Some children from the marginal classes might not
realise this and remain silent in school.
This shows the key effects of power in
distributing recognition rules. However,
even if we recognise that the context is specific,
we still might find it difficult to produce
legitimate communication, and again children of
the marginal classes find themselves in this
position: 'they may not possess the realization
rule'. As a result, 'they will not have
acquired the legitimate pedagogic code, but they
will have acquired their place in the
classificatory system'. This is the main
experience of school for them.
Recognition rules enable appropriate realizations,
but realization rules are required to actually put
meanings together and make them public, producing
legitimate text. This can be affected by the
different values of framing. We therefore
have an explanation of classification as a result
of power, and framing values as the result of
control [rather as translations of them, selecting
and distributing recognition and realization
rules]. However, pedagogic practice 'is
essentially' interactive, defined by
classification and framing procedures. The
acquirer is expected to construct legitimate text,
which may cover only 'how one sits or how one
moves', since 'the text is anything which attracts
evaluation' (18). Evaluation itself is a
condensed version of the pedagogic code, its
classification and framing procedures, and the
relationships of power and control that have
produce them. However, texts can change
interactional practices, that is change
classification and framing values [no
examples?].[So texts must have or be a power of
their own?]
Some research can illustrate the relevance of all
this, including some done by Holland [already
discussed here].
Here the interest is in how context and tasks
produce different readings, including tacit
ones. Here the exercise turned on
classifying food items as a kind of general
issue. Pictures were sorted differently by
samples of working class and middle class
children. Formally, the task can be
described as weakly classified and framed, since
children were told to choose any picture and
classify them in any way they liked. They
gave two types of reason, one referring to the
life context [something they had for breakfast for
example], and one relying on more abstract
classifications [they are vegetables]. This
is not just a difference between abstract and
concrete thinking because we would then 'lose
sight of the social basis of that difference' (19)
[what a classic way to put it - we can't accept
one term because we want to see social class
differences]. We can trace these
classifications in terms of direct relations or
indirect relations 'to a specific material base',
the local context and local experience.
Initially middle class children offered indirect
reasons, but when all the children were asked to
sort the cards again, they were able to switch
back to a direct relation to local experience,
although working class kids were not. So it
looks like middle class kids have two principles
of classification, 'which stood in a hierarchical
relation to each other'- why did middle class kids
choose the indirect form first?
Apparently it depends on how you read the coding
instructions. Middle class kids realized
that in that particular context, classifications
were still expected to be strong between school
knowledge and common sense knowledge. They
had a better understanding of the recognition rule
that said there was a strong classification
between home and school, 'itself based on the
dominance of the official pedagogic practice'
(20). This gave middle class kids more
relative power and privilege.
In another example, secondary schools responded
differently to the 1988 Educational Reform Act and
the introduction of cross curricular themes.
These have arisen as a result of criticism of the
narrow subject based curriculum. Students
talked about these themes differently, however,
some in terms of subject conventions and others in
terms of topic orientations and concrete
examples. Again there were social class
differences [but were they significant? The
totals actually look quite close]. Bernstein
says it's not clear how this happened, but he says
there is a school effect, and one school in
particular taught themes in subject-based
ways. There can also be an interaction with
social class. In any event, strong
classification and framing defeats the ostensible
purpose of cross curricular themes.
Weakening a classification between school
knowledge and every day knowledge 'could lead to a
perception on the part of the student that themes
were not really official pedagogic discourse, as
the researchers found' (21). [Actually the
extract isn't terribly clear in my view, but
Bernstein says it shows that some students are
aware of subject based recognition and realization
rules - Rancière
would have a field day with this!].
These examples show the 'empirical relevance' of
the models, which show how power and control
'translate into pedagogic codes and their
modalities'. (22). Bernstein also
thinks he has 'shown how these codes are acquired
and so shape consciousness'[ridiculously
ambitious]. He has linked macro structures
of power and micro processes of the formation of
pedagogic consciousness. The models reveal
order and change, but above all they 'make
possible specific descriptions of the pedagogising
process and their outcomes'[well he has generated
number of possibilities by combining structure and
options]. Now we need to look at the
construction of pedagogic discourse.
Appendix.
The model has been criticised because it doesn't
adequately describe organisational or
administrative dimensions. The organisation
can be seen as the container for something that is
transmitted, and thus offers 'the primary
condition without which no transmission can be
stable and reproduced' (23). There is a
necessary level of administration of staff and
resources and the management of external
responsibilities. The relation between these
and the transmitting agents affect the shape of
the container. Changes in classification and
framing can affect the government of educational
institutions and therefore affect the shape of the
container, and pedagogic codes can be relatively
stable or unstable, producing different levels of
conflict and consensus. This in turn will
require different levels of management.
However the management of resources itself, the
'economy of the container', is not always related
to the code modality, and can deal with different
code modalities. There are other effects
independent of code modality, extrinsic to
them. These can be seen as 'external biases
imposed by some power (e.g. State)'(24).
This complicates the picture and the metaphor of
the container and the contained, since 'bias
operates at a different level as it mediates
between some external power and the internal
regulation of the agency'. We therefore need
to identify the parameters involved - 'bias,
shape, stability, economy' and develop a new
concept to include them. To some extent, we
can use the old notions of distributive rules to
cover resources as well as discourses. We
can extend the notion of regulative discourse to
include management functions and even external
biases. However, we need a concept that
shows how it can regulate pedagogic code while
also being dependent on it [!], to show how the
fundamental 'mode of being of the agency' is
regulated. The notion of 'pedagogic culture'
will do this, reflecting the way in which agencies
cope with bias, shape, stability and
economy. [So nothing falsifies or tests the
model - we just generate endless ad hoc hypotheses
to incorporate criticism]
Chapter 2. The Pedagogic Device
We want the general principles that govern the
transformation of knowledge into pedagogic
communication, whatever the knowledge might be [in
other words very general abstract principles
again, and not actual effective rules in empirical
circumstances]. This could be unnecessary
because we have some empirical understandings, but
these are often see pedagogic communication as a
mere carrier for external power relations or
ideology, or for skills and legitimate
identities. If we are to study what is
actually carried or relayed we have to examine
'social grammar, without which no message is
possible' (25).
The language device has several formulations, but
basically it examines how roles are acquired and
how interaction is regulated. For Chomsky,
this device is independent of culture, existing
'at the level of the social but not at the level
of the cultural' (26). It has just evolved
and 'we could not leave a device as critical as
this to the vagueness and vicissitudes of
culture'. [The diagrams are very limited,
with meaning potential at one end and
communication at the other, with black boxes
called language device and pedagogic device
respectively in the middle. There is also a
feedback loop which acts 'either in a restricted
or in an enhancing fashion'. Since rules
vary with the context, there are contextual rules
to understand local communications [!]. They
are relatively stable over time but contextually
regulated.
One question which arises is whether this affects
the apparent neutrality of the language device,
[whether there are some emergent effects].
Halliday has argued that these roles are not
'ideologically free, but that the rules reflect
emphases on the meaning potential created by
dominant groups' (27). Perhaps it is these
dominant interests that produce the relative
stability of the rules. [As well] language
and speech are dialectically interrelated.
This is a complex argument and there are
contradictory views about it.
At one level the language device clearly has some
built in classifications, especially gender
classifications, and gender equality suffers from
having to work with these in built classifications
[the example is the term 'mastery'] [gender is
never mentioned again from what I can see].
So both the carrier and the carried have
contextual rules and neither 'is ideologically
free'.
Turning to the pedagogic device, we can also
identify the internal rules that regulate
pedagogic communication which 'acts selectively on
the meaning potential', the latter referring to
all discourse that can be pedagogised. The
pedagogic device continuously restricts or
enhances realizations of potential pedagogic
meaning. The formal structure is similar to
the linguistic device [because he has drawn it
this way]. There are rules to regulate
realization and these rules are intrinsic and
relatively stable, although they 'are not
ideologically free' (28). They are
'implicated in the distribution of', and constrain
forms of consciousness. Both language device
and pedagogic device are sites for conflict and
control, but only the pedagogic device can produce
an outcome 'which can subvert the fundamental
rules of the device'[surely not so, we can produce
challenging avant-garde linguistic utterances as
well. This is Bernstein's implicit
functionalism again?].
The pedagogic device provides the 'intrinsic
grammar of pedagogic discourse' where grammar is
used 'in a metaphoric sense' [clear as forking
mud]. This grammar is realized through
distributive rules, recontextualizing rules, and
evaluative rules. [I am still trying to
figure out what I find difficult about this notion
of a rule rather than a convention or a constraint
- is it that rule implies some structural,
consensual, functional operation?]. These
rules are related and they also feature power
relationships between them [a continuing ambiguity
about power as well]. Distributive rules
particularly regulate relations 'between power,
social groups, forms of consciousness and
practice'; recontextualizing rules 'regulate the
formation of specific pedagogic discourse';
evaluative rules 'constitute any pedagogic
practice', since the purpose of pedagogic practice
is to 'transmit criteria', and this provides 'a
ruler for consciousness'[compare this with
dispositions in Bourdieu, which are socially
sedimented, unconscious, and embodied]. [This
argument means instructional and regulative
discourse are also organized in a hierachy as we
shall see -- separate arguments are really the
same argument. This is an axiomatic system]
There are two different classes of knowledge that
'are necessarily available in all societies' and
are 'intrinsic to language itself' - the thinkable
and the unthinkable. This provides two
classes of knowledge, the esoteric and the
mundane, or the 'knowledge of the other' and 'the
otherness of knowledge' [all of them variants of
the sacred and profane?]. There is also the
knowledge of the possible and the possibility of
the impossible. The line dividing these two
classes varies historically and culturally.
If we compare small scale non literate societies
with more complex ones, religion regulates the
division between the thinkable and the
unthinkable, but in 'a very brutal simplification'
(29), it is the 'upper reaches of the educational
system' these do not always originate divisions,
but they control and manage them. The mere
thinkable is still within schools.
However simple and complex societies have a
similar order of meaning [a key functionalist
assumption again]. It would be wrong to see
it as an abstract vs. concrete division, since
'all meanings are abstract'. However, the
abstraction takes different forms. In all
cases it 'postulates and relates two worlds', the
material and the immaterial, the mundane and the
transcendental. What this means is that
meanings have different relations to the 'specific
material base', a direct one where meanings are
'wholly consumed by the context' (30), and an
indirect one, which both create new meanings and
unite the two worlds. This division is
reflected in a division of labour and a set of
social relationships [and not the other way
about].
Indirect meanings produce a 'potential discursive
gap', but this is not a dislocation.
Instead, it offers alternative possibilities and
realizations, offering a space for the unthinkable
and impossible, something yet to be thought, and
this is both 'beneficial and dangerous at the same
time'. Any distribution of power tries to
regulate the realization of this potential, since
it must be regulated [for social order, but
particular groups are also able to follow their
own interests in preventing alternatives].
The religious systems of simple societies are a
good example. The 'paradox' of the gap
[between beneficial than harmful outcomes, I
assume] is covered by distributive rules which
govern those who can access the site.
[Another?] paradox arises because the device
itself cannot do this effectively, and
contradictions are 'rarely totally suppressed',
and the pedagogic process itself reveals the
possibility of the gap and makes power relations
visible. There is a connection with the
notion of field, which is constituted by
distributive rules, which are 'controlled more and
more today by the state itself'(31).
Recontextualizing rules govern what counts as
adequate pedagogic discourse, specialized
communications. Pedagogic discourse itself
is 'the rule which embeds two discourses',
relating to skills of various kinds and to social
order, instructional and regulative
discourse. Bernstein thinks that
instructional discourses are always embedded in
regulative discourse which is the dominant one
[repetition of what he said above].
Pedagogic discourse combines the two, so it is
wrong to separate the transmission of skills and
the transmissions of values - 'the secret voice of
this device is to disguise the fact that there is
only one' discourse (32). [Is this ideology
as well? Or maybe a latent function?]
Pedagogic discourse appears as neutral compared to
the familiar subject based discourses. So we
need to redefine it as a principle not a discourse
[why not say that originally, dick], regulating
the connection between the other discourses.
However, it does give rise to a specialised
discourse of its own [!]. It also creates a
gap between discourses and the pedagogised sites
or forms, and again we have 'a space in
which ideology can play. No discourse ever
moves without ideology at play'[ideology here
means the disguised interests of powerful groups?
Or just 'worldview'?] This move also turns it into
'an imaginary discourse', a mediated or virtual
one. It also produces 'imaginary subjects'
(33) [a note on this distinction between the real
and the imaginary says it is supposed to draw
attention to an activity unmediated by anything
other than itself, compared to one when mediation
is intrinsic in practice. The example is
between carpentry and its pedagogic equivalent,
'woodwork'. Real discourses are related to
the social base again. Presumably, then they
are also restricted in what can be thought -
practice itself can never produce new
possibilities for thinking? All manual
occupations seem to produce some kind of
mechanical solidarity].
We can put this in formal terms - 'pedagogic
discourse is a recontextualizing principle',
selecting, and organising other discourses, but
never identified with them. This is 'a
recontextualizing discourse', and it creates
'recontextualizing fields' with suitable agents
'with practicing ideologies'[ideology here appears
to be world view?]. Recontextualization
creates 'the fundamental autonomy of
education'. There is even an 'official
recontextualizing field' operated by the state,
and a 'pedagogic recontextualizing field'
inhabited by specialist educators, and this
provides the relative autonomy and struggle [none
within the state? No regulation of the
specialist educators by the state - he admits that
today the state is attempting to weaken the PRF].
Since moral discourse creates the criteria for
subsequent instructional discourse, we can see
that in general regulative discourses affect the
order in instructional discourses. [repetition
again really, going from a specific case to some
underlying principle or rule]. We can see
this with physics. We distinguish between physics
as the production of the discourse, and physics as
a pedagogic discourse: the former displays
variety, but the latter is controlled by devices
such as textbooks, written by pedagogues and only
'rarely physicists'. As a result, there is
no formal logical link between the discourses,
since pedagogues select. The selection also
depends on how physics is to be related to the
other subjects, how is to be sequenced and paced,
and these 'cannot be derived from the logic of the
discourse of physics or its various activities'[so
this is almost the opposite of the 'powerful
knowledge' merchants' argument that school
curriculum, at least, should reflect the vertical
hierarchical structures of proper sciences?
Or perhaps they are just saying we should design
the curriculum and let pedagogues figure out how
to teach it?]. The rules for the
transmission of physics have a reality of their
own - they are 'social facts' (34), inevitably
incorporating selection [weird]. [Somehow]
the overall regulative functions of the discourse
provide the rules of the internal order of
instructional discourse - it is dominant [I think
this is just saying that pedagogues have to work
with objects that are already selected as being
important, as social facts. Whether
Bernstein means this in the full Durkheim sense is
not clear - it still seems to imply some consensus
or some powerful imposition of a consensus.
Hasn't the discourse of physics itself done much
to undermine this? And is almost a way of
saying that the objects in pedagogy are indeed
arbitrary?].
Recontextualizing principles also produce a theory
of instruction. This is never 'entirely
instrumental' since it also imports from the
regulative discourse models of learners and
teachers and their relation.
Pedagogic discourse has to be transformed into
pedagogic practice. This involves a
specialist notion of time, a text and a space and
their interrelationship. This takes the form
of 'very fundamental category relations' and again
these have 'implications for the deepest cultural
level' (35) [all this follows as another
implication from the connection between pedagogic
discourse and regulative discourse, between
pedagogic order and social order in
general]. Pedagogic discourses can operate
at a very fine level, producing, for example the
notion of age stages to punctuate time, although
these are 'wholly imaginary and arbitrary'
(35). Both text and spaces are also
organized into a specific context, but again
behind the specifics stand more abstract
levels. Beneath lies another level, that of
actual pedagogic practice and pedagogic
communication, which features acquisition,
evaluation, and transmission, where the 'key to
pedagogic practice is continuous evaluation'(36).
The pedagogic device condenses these levels,
providing an overall 'symbolic ruler for
consciousness' [consciousness is assumed to follow
from pedagogic practice]. It is a form of
religious practice with its descending levels to
control the unthinkable. [Gives the Durkheimian
game away. The wonderful diagram on page 36
indicates the full story, where ID is
instructional discourse, RD is regulative
discourse, and dividing them by a horizontal line
does not indicate division, but embeddedness.
Why practice should be an indicator of a pedagogic
code with its modalities is still a puzzle
- why use the term code at all unless you wish to
imply some structural determination? Note that
codes relating to the (un)thinkable do not appear
where they should in the diagram below -- on the
left even before social groups. There seem to be
no feedback loops now either]. We can see
homologies between religion and education.
We can follow Max Weber here as well, with his
division between prophets priests and laity being
homologous to producers, reproducers and
acquirers. There is a 'rule' that people can
only occupy one category at a time, and that while
prophets and priests are in opposition, priests
and the laity are in relations of 'natural
affinity' [Bernstein is only implying that these
social relations affects the pedagogic field too -
I would have said there is opposition between all
three categories].
We now have an even better a model of the
pedagogic device on page 37 showing the
connections between social groups and various
rules and fields and processes.
This is how consciousness is regulated [this is
actually only assumed to follow from processes,
although it is already smuggled in with evaluation
rules], and cultural transmitted. However
there is no determinism and there are sources of
indeterminacy:
Internally the
device controls the unthinkable, but in the very
process of doing so 'makes the possibility of
the unthinkable available' [deviance is the same
as the principle of conformity in Durkheim's
terms] (38). Externally the distribution
of power outside itself has potential challenges
and oppositions, and the device shows this
background struggle: it 'creates an arena
or of struggle for those who are to appropriate
it'.
Overall, the claim is that Bernstein has exposed
'the intrinsic grammar of the device' and its
'hidden voice'. As it processes, it
regulates. Its ' [very] grammar... codes
order and position' while at the same time
containing a potential for transformation.
Another note discusses the French System where
university staff circulates to the lycée as a rare
exception to the strong classification between
those who produce discourse and those who
recontextualize it. However,
recontextualizers rarely go the other way, and
this might be preserved by increasing distinctions
between research only and teaching only
institutions in the UK. Another note points
out that the texts produced by pedagogy are also
imaginary. Unlike the texts of producers,
they are not expected to be original and
unique. Pedagogic texts instead offer
'intra-textuality [in the] process of constructing
unique authorship'.
[Overall, I'm not surprise that this article has
been so controversial, and so tidied up in
commentaries. Apart from the massive
assumptions, principally about consciousness and
about the effects of social context in limiting
what can be thought, there is a clear functional
argument throughout. By and large, power is
necessary for order, even though it occasionally
has to be adjusted through functional
conflicts. This is also an interesting text
for people like Maton who want to accuse Bourdieu
of operating only with the arbitrary - it is hard
to tell because Bernstein uses ideology in
different terms, but it looks as if there is an
arbitrary social order behind all these
developments as well, at least once the basic
paramters have been established. The non-arbitrary
in Bernstein only amounts to social facts like the
split between the sacred and the profane.
Certainly, pedagogy is arbitrary compared to the
operation of real discourses. I suppose that
by calling them real discourses, you might think
that Bernstein is some kind of social realist, but
he insists that that only means that they are
closely connected to their material bases: this is
a theory of verisimilitude at best].
Chapter 3 Pedagogising Knowledge: studies in
recontextualizing
[At last! Some concrete detail. This is a very
good discussion of the neolibleral turn, but with
only an implicit marxism. All the terms introduced
in the above are just used descriptively]
Titles [that is academic classifications] relate
more to positions in intellectual fields than to
the content of actual arguments, so this one could
have been called anything with functionalist,
Althusserian, Foucaldian or postmodern resonances
[strikes me as both defensive and arrogant].
In the 1960s, there was a notable shift towards
the notion of agent or member competence in a
number of different intellectual fields, and
this had consequences for pedagogy. We're
not going to discuss the origin of the convergence
[shame, because it doesn't seem to have been
predicted in the earlier work]. Competences
'are intrinsically creative and tacitly acquired
in informal interactions. They are practical
accomplishments' (42), somehow they escape power
relations, and agents can now negotiate social
order and interact with various kinds of cognitive
and linguistic structures. They are assumed
to be culture free. They 'embrace populism'.
There is an implicit logic that says that all
people are inherently competent and that there are
common procedures with no deficits; the subject is
active and creative; the subject is self
regulating and this is benign; this brings
skepticism towards hierarchy and emancipation;
there is a focus on the present tense as the most
relevant time. These characteristics can
apply unevenly but most of them are present.
It is an 'idealism of competence, a celebration of
what we are' (43), but it involves an abstract
individual somehow outside power and
control. The idea clearly resonates with the
liberal progressive and radical ideologies of the
1960s and was taken up by those in education, even
though most of those formulating their theory were
not really concerned with education. The
position also entered conflicts in the
intellectual field, and were crucial in taking on
various opposing positions, including 'Piaget on
behaviourism, Garfinkel and structural
functionalism'. Structuralism even in Levi
Strauss was one strand, but there was also
ethnomethodology and other strands in
sociolinguistics. There was a common anti
positivism. Somehow, these arguments became
important to the theory and practice of education,
including members of the official
recontextualizing field, as in the Plowden Report,
as well as among the expert pedagogues 'an unusual
convergence'. At the same time, different
inflections applied more to different educational
disciplines - Piaget to educational psychology,
for example.
This led to a specific pedagogic practice
especially in primary and preschools areas,
constituting 'a competence model' and struggling
with its opposite 'the performance model', based
on specific outputs particular texts and
specialized skills. [A diagram on page 45
tries to refer back to classification as well,
especially with the main issues of space time and
discourse]. In more detail:
At the level of discourse, competence
models favour 'projects, themes, ranges of
experience, a group base', acquirer control,
celebration of difference rather than
stratification, weak classification.
Performance models offer specialised subjects,
'skills, procedures which are clearly marked with
respect of form and function'. Acquirers
have less control and their texts are graded and
ranked. There is strong classification.
In terms of space, competence models do
not distinguish specially defined pedagogic spaces
and allow acquirers to construct different spaces
and to circulate between them.
Classification is weak. In performance
models there are clear boundaries and markings and
regulations, with strong classification. In terms
of time, competence model see the present
tense as the major mode. Time is not
particularly punctuated or marked, nor is the
future particularly emphasized. Weak pacing
also features. Only the teacher can know
what each acquirer is revealing a particular
moment, and uses this as the basis for provision.
When it comes to evaluation, competence
models again emphasise what is present in the
product, using diffuse and implicit criteria of
evaluation. However, there is more emphasis
on regulated discourse criteria of conduct and
manner. In performance models the emphasis
is upon what is missing in the product, referring
to explicit and specific criteria for legitimate
text.
For control, children do not have their
experience structured by space, time or discourses
and positional control is a low priority.
Control is likely to 'inhere in personalised
forms', hence forms of communication 'which focus
upon the intentions, dispositions, relations and
reflexivity of the acquirer' (47). This is
the most favoured mode. In performance
models, space time and discourse do structure and
classifying and therefore 'constitute and relay
order'. Instructional discourse
disciplines. A more economical form of
control appears, not personalised. Neither
of these techniques work smoothly necessarily, and
acquirer subversions are 'mode specific'.
Pedagogic text in competence models is not
seen as a product of the acquirer, but rather
something that reveals their development and can
be diagnosed by the professional teacher, drawing
on suitable 'social and psychological sciences
which legitimise this pedagogic mode'
(46-7). It follows that these meanings are
available only to professionals. In
performance modes, the focus is on the text itself
as the performance of the acquirer, and
professional teachers offer explicit pedagogy ease
and professional grading. The emphasis is on
both past and future. But the pedagogic
practice itself constructs the past for the
acquirer.
Notions of autonomy vary, competence
models assume a wide range of autonomy, although
teacher autonomy is often compromised because they
all have to practice the same pedagogy.
There are also context dependent elements which
require local autonomy. There is no reliance
on outside pedagogic resources like
textbooks. There is less availability for
public scrutiny and accountability, especially as
outputs are difficult to evaluate. There is
no strong tie to predetermined futures either [so
no coaching for grammar school or
university]. There are different performance
modalities, some relate to the future,
'introverted modalities' and some relate more to
external regulation, 'extroverted
modalities'. The first looks like the
exploration of the specialised discourse itself is
autonomous, whereas the second one relates to
something external like the economy or the job
market. At the same time, even introverted
modalities are subordinate to external
curriculum. There can be individual
variation at the level of teaching practice aimed
at increasing performance, although external
criteria limit this autonomy. The need to
market institutions can also produce a certain
kind of autonomy [well, market variation at
least].
There is an economic factor. The
costs of competence models are higher, and so are
the cost of training teachers in the 'theoretical
basis of competency models' (49) [selecting people
for teacher training is also 'likely to be
stricter' because the qualities required are
'restricted and tacit']. There is a
substantial cost in terms of time and the
construction of pedagogic resources, and in
evaluating each acquirer. Parents have to be
socialised, extensive feedback is required on
development, teachers have to interact a lot in
order to plan and monitor. Usually, it is
the individual, committed teacher who bears these
costs, and this can lead to 'ineffective pedagogic
practice' due to teacher fatigue.
Transmission costs of performance models are
relatively lower for all those reasons.
Accountability can also be managed more
objectively. Performance can sometimes be
routinized [these days, put online]. It is
easier to regulate the costs and to impose other
controls. A different kind of commitment and
motivation is required.
We can spell out the differences in more
detail. Competence models stress the
similarities between people which are seen as
complementary. However, this splits into
three different options. The first one,
'liberal/progressive' is located within the
individual and to things that all individual
share. It intended to emancipate the new
notion of the child away from the old repressive
forms of authority, based on a 'new science of
child development'(50). The caring ethos
opened professional careers for women and attacked
patriarchy. Individual potential was to be
released. Advocates and sponsors included
the new middle class 'in the field of symbolic
control'[referring to empirical examples of these
correspondences? - in class codes
and control vol. 3].
The second model looks at similarities within a
local culture and it is that local culture which
is usually dominated, but which has hidden
communicative competences. This is the
populist mode. The third mode agrees that
competence is found in local dominated groups or
classes, but focuses on various material and
symbolic opportunities to overcome domination and
achieve emancipation. This is the radical
mode, associated with Freire, and 'often found in
adult informal education' (51)
Although these competence models share a focus on
similarities, they are often found opposed within
the pedagogic recontextualizing field. They
all feature an invisible pedagogy. The
radical mode is not found at all in the official
recontextualizing field, and only appears in the
PRF if there is sufficient autonomy.
Performance models also differ according to how
their texts are specialized. They emphasize
'"different from" relations'. They are
'empirically normal across all levels of official
education', so that competence models can be seen
as resistance or interruptions.
The variables for performance models include
whether they are singular or regional, with the
former offering much stronger boundaries and
hierarchies in the intellectual field its
practices, its examination and its licences.
Regions follow where singulars are
recontextualized into larger units [some examples
are given, but not the principle, apparently much
depends on the social base]. They threaten
the culture of singulars and include 'journalism,
dance, sport, tourism' (52). Modular forms
also help. Regionalization opens the
structure to greater central control, but they
must also remain autonomous in terms of content so
they can be more responsive to markets. The
classification of discourses is weakened, and so
is subject identity, which becomes 'projected'
rather than 'introjected'. These trends are
less obvious in schools, and cross curricular
themes have been resisted.
There is also a generic performance mode,
operating outside pedagogic recontextualizing
fields, as in the innovations introduced by the
Manpower Services Commission or the Training
Agency. These became 'the distinctive
"competences" methodology', as in NVQs. They
focus on work and life outside school. They
are located primarily in further education, and
this transformed the professional culture of FE
and weakened 'both the liberal education and
technical craft tradition'. They also
feature misrecognition, seeming to be based on a
functional analysis yielding specific
competencies, thus borrowing from the competence
model. In the process, they have rejected
any notion of a cultural basis for stills tasks
practices and areas of work and have produced 'a
jejune concept of trainability'[so who
misrecognises here? Does he thinks that
teachers and students are taken in by this sort of
hijack? Why is this a misrecognised version
and not just a hybrid version? Another
option is offered below in terms of a shift back
from competence to performance mode].
All this tells us something about the potential of
the recontextualizing field in the contemporary
context [rendered as 'I am now in a position to
construct the discursive potential of the
recontextualizing field which characterises the
contemporary context', 53]. These examples
show the increased importance of 'the dominant
ideology in the ORF', and the elements of relative
autonomy in the PRF. They reveal oppositions
within recontextualizing fields. There are
however shared preoccupations - competency models
stress development of consciousness, are
therapeutic, and 'are directly linked to symbolic
control' [that is emphasize the symbolic and
cultural] (54), while performance modes are more
directly linked to the economy.
The emergence of a range of singulars arises from
the division of discursive labour, and that in
turn is tied to English nationalism and
imperialism, including the development of
economics and social sciences, 'linked to the new
technologies of the market and the management of
subjectivities' [not much evidence here].
Classics was linked to entry to the administrative
levels of the civil service, science is linked to
material technologies. This is the 'profane
face' of the development of subjects, compared to
its 'sacred face' which claims otherness and
dedicated identities, the notion of a
calling. Singulars create strong boundaries
and introjected 'narcissistic' identities
(55). Regions also face both ways, linking
with the professions outside as well as addressing
the need to group singulars. They are likely
to become the modal form. [Compare this with
the desperate struggles for status inside and
outside the official university hierarchy in Bourdieu, where
addressing the cultural industries became a
strategy for marginalised academics]. New
regions particularly face outwards and therefore
have to relate to the requirements of external
practices, providing a projected identity.
Those practices will affect this identity: it is a
volatile context. Generic performance is
complex. It features 'similar to' relations
like competence modes, but finds this in terms of
general skills, linked to the market and flexible
performance, providing projected identities again.
We can classify them [diagram page 56] in terms of
the sorts of control and discourse they
feature. Control refers to therapeutic or
economic functions, and discourse to pedagogic
modes [liberal, radical, populist]; specialist
performance produces different possibilities for
identity and control, and the context outside can
act in different ways even on apparently
autonomous modes, from external determination, to
pragmatic embrace. These tensions can
sometimes be managed by classifying strongly
introjected and projected elements [especially
with modular schemes, theoretical and practical
modules] [Bernstein again uses terms like
dependency being 'masked', or the need to
interpret exigencies]. The modes can be
mixed as well, including a case where 'the
therapeutic mode may be inserted in an economic
mode, retaining its original name and resonances,
while giving rise to an opposing practice'[which
seems to cover all the possibilities]. The
state can embrace particular modes, as with
Plowden.
Competency modes became dominant in the late
1960s. The obvious resonance with
emancipatory ideologies is not the sole
explanation. The main factor turns on
relative autonomy for the PRF at the time,
especially in terms of training teachers.
The government changed the particular form of
schools, moving towards comprehensives, for
example but 'pedagogic discourse was not the
subject of legislation' (57). However, 'an
autonomous local space for the construction of
curriculum' was created. The abolition of
selection removed one crucial external regulator,
since selective grammar schools had upheld
performance modes, usually in terms of collections
of singulars. The focus was on something
that the acquirer did not already possess, with an
emphasis upon the text to be acquired.
Learning was considered in terms of behaviourism
and atomism. As school organisation turned
to a weaker form of classification, a space was
opened up and it was not subject to state
regulation. At both primary and secondary
levels the competence mode emerged and was
legitimised by trends in the pedagogic field.
Performance modes were attacked as being based on
the concept of deficit. Therapeutic emphases
focused on empowerment in different ways,
individual, cultural and political, and these were
in opposition. These discourses are filled
the gap and some were embraced by the ORF. As the
population bulge appeared, colleges of education
expanded and were subject to fewer controls,
including over selection. At the same time,
theoretical discourses were becoming more
specialized. At school level teacher
shortages reduced the selective power of
management. Full employment put the emphasis
on social relations like multiculturalism and
leisure, together, these produced new
agendas. At one stage, there was even
'ideological rapport'between the pedagogic field
and the ORF [plowden]
In the 1970s, the state moved to intervene,
largely through centralised monitoring and
funding, and this 'changed the culture of
educational institutions', from the increasing
management to more explicit criteria for staff
appointments. The role of the market
increased and schools were seen to be adding
value. Local authorities were stripped of
responsibilities. Overall, the PRF lost
autonomy, and new discourses were introduced to
teacher training, including 'management,
assessment' (58). There is also more school
based training. Overall, there was a shift
to performance models by the ORF, imposed more
rigorously, although this varied in different
levels of education.
Generic modes came to the fore based on a
particularly short term conception of work and
life, reflecting the need to be flexible and
trainable over a lifetime. Everyone now
needs to acquire the ability to be taught and to
respond effectively, with 'concurrent,
subsequent, intermittent pedagogics' (59),
producing 'a pedagogized future'. Actors
have to find their own meanings from their past
and future, and therefore require a specialised
identity as 'the dynamic interface between
individual career is and the social or collective
basis'. This is not just a matter of
individual psychology or ambition, but the product
of a particular social order offering other
identities 'of reciprocal recognition, supports,
mutual legitimization, and finally through a
negotiated collective purpose'. Trainability
is 'empty'.
The identity is supported in consumption, and we
can see the products of the market as 'signifiers
whereby temporary stabilities, orientations,
relations and evaluations are constructed'.
This generic mode is extended from its base in
manual practices to other areas of work. The
main pedagogic objective is to produce
trainability. This involves the production
and reproduction of 'imaginary concepts of work
and life which abstract such experiences from the
power relations of their lived conditions and
negates the possibilities of understanding and
criticism'[could be Bourdieu again].
The practice seems to be driven by an increased
official control, even in higher education, where
it works indirectly, through funding and through
research, and in some cases 'industrial niche'
(60). This stratified institutions.
Intellectual development can involve acquiring
academic stars, and this has been a brake on
regionalism. Those lower down have been
forced to market their pedagogic discourse, and
develop projected identities.
Regionalization is increased here. Thus
practices have affected staff student and
institutional identity, and increased diversity
and stratification. The move to
modularization has assisted this. This
offers a difference with performance modes in
primary and secondary levels.
The national curriculum has clearly introduced
stronger classification based on a collection of
singulars, and there is increased stake
monitoring. However, framing has weakened
with the importance of coursework
assessment. Somehow 'schools may well
exploit such weaker framing over evaluation as a
means of increasing their performance' (61) [teach
to the test?]. Curriculum monitoring is more
central, but schools now have greater autonomy
over the budget and administration.
Management focuses on performance, whatever the
pedagogic discourse, and managerialism has
affected all educational institutions, including a
greater regulation of selection and
promotion. The big dislocation these days is
between the culture of pedagogy and management
culture, producing a certain 'retrospective'
element of pedagogic culture and a prospective one
for management. The state seems to have
embedded both, and the result might well be 'a
state promoted instrumentality', despite the
implicit claims for the intrinsic value of
knowledge in the school curriculum. However,
there are other influences.
One note says that the research selectivity
exercise is altering the type of research and
publication, away from long-term basic research to
short term applied research 'with low risks and
rapid publication' (63), and this will have
effects on both the orientation of teaching and
the knowledge base of the students. It has
produced a new culture, 'reproduced by new actors
with new motivations' .
Chapter 4 Official Knowledge and pedagogic
Identities: the politics of recontextualization
[More detail about identities, using the same sort
of framework as above. Bernstein introduces
this one as but a mere sketch, but tells us he is
a hero who likes to live dangerously].
Official knowledge reveals different biases and
focuses with the intention of constructing in
teachers and students a particular disposition
embedded in particular performances and
practices. Abstract analysis produces four
possible positions. Pedagogic identity
follows from 'embedding a career in a collective
base'(66) and a career can have knowledge, moral
and locational dimensions. The collective
basis refers to the social order in schools as
institutionalised by the state. Major
changes in bases and careers have occurred, and
these are 'international, national, domestic,
economic, educational or leisure' contexts, and
curriculum reform follows as a response to these
changes. Four different approaches to manage
change are possible, and these take the form of
pedagogic identities. There is a struggle to
institutionalise them.
Two identities are generated by state resources,
and two from local resources, where institutions
have relative autonomy (centred and
decentred). The diagram on 67 shows the four
possibilities. Identities may be
restricted/retrospective, or selected/prospective
at the state level, and differentiated/decentred
(market) or integrated/decentred (therapeutic) at
the local level. These different positions
may both oppose and collaborate with each other,
and there is a struggle to legitimate some and
exclude others.
The restricted/retrospective identity is a
conservative one, insulated from economic change,
with the control exercised over 'discursive
inputs', or contents, and not outputs. They
are 'formed by' hierarchical strongly bounded and
sequenced discourses and practices, and they refer
to a collective social based in the past, as
recovered by some grand narrative. This past
has to be stabilised and preserved in the
future. This becomes urgent in times of
particular secular change, for example in the
Middle East or the Russian federation.
Selected/prospective identities also refer
to the past, but not the same one. It has a
more positive stance towards a dealing with
change, and it does this by selecting elements of
the past and linking it to economic
performance. Thatcherism is a good example,
with its emphasis on Victorian values and
individual enterprise. This time, individual
careers are foregrounded. Exchange value
dominates the judgement of performance, and this
requires control over both inputs' to education
and outputs. New Labour also launched a new
prospective identity in comparison to the old
retrospective one of old labour, stressing
preserving communities with participating in the
economic sphere.
The local decentred identities depend on
institutional autonomy. This autonomy are
either leads to some therapeutic outcome, or a new
flexibility in terms of the market. In both
cases, the emphasis is on the present, although
these are different presents. In the
therapeutic identity, the main stress is on
'personal, cognitive and social development, often
labelled progressive'(68). It features 'a
control invisible to the student', and stresses
autonomous flexible thinking and social relations
in teamwork. It is costly. It is
currently weak on the national scene, and its
sponsoring social group has little power.
The identity it offers participants opposes
specialisation and stratification, offers weak
boundaries, soft management, power 'disguised by
communication networks and interpersonal
relations'(70), and ideally, 'stable, integrated
identities with adaptable cooperative practices'.
The decentred market identity is not yet fully
realized [it is now]. It occur in
educational institutions with a lot of autonomy
over the use of the budget and organisation.
These aim at attracting students in a competitive
environment, meeting external performance
criteria, attempting to optimise its market
position [exactly like Marjon, suitably scaled
down] the same goes for a department or groups
inside the institutions. Everything depends
on the market. There is an unaccountable
hierarchical management system operating allegedly
technically, and monitoring the distribution of
resources according to the effectiveness of local
groups. The institutional identity focuses
on exchange value of the product in a market, and
there is an attempt to maximize inputs' .
The focus is short term and extrinsic, vocational
rather than based on exploring knowledge.
Flexibility is crucial, so that 'personal
commitment and particular dedication of staff and
students are regarded as resistances' (69), seen
as a restrictive practice. Relations are
characterised by contract.
Universities themselves might be stratified
according to these different identities, with the
elite ones able to acquire academic stars to
develop the old claims to power and position, with
[personal?] identities which can be defined as
related to 'introjection [of] knowledge'. In
non elite institutions, the organisation becomes
'discursive' as the main way to maintain market
positions [that is with flexible discourses to
create different packages and permutations].
Identities here work through projection, driven by
external forces.
We can use the terms in the diagram to recognise
the effects of contemporary educational
reforms. These have combined centralised
control, such as the 'standardisation of knowledge
inputs', and local autonomy. Originally,
there was a 'complementary relation' (71) between
retrospective conservatives and neoliberal
marketisers, but also some tension, for example
over whether a centralised national curriculum was
required - the retrospective seem to have won out
here, although there is also an inclusion of basic
skills and other 'vocational insertions'. It
was the professional pedagogues driving the market
identity, with some support from civil servants,
although this was not strong enough to completely
prevail - for example the original intention for
'complex profiling forms of assessment' ended up
with simple tests. Thematic links between
traditional subjects were also ineffective [with
the same study by Whitty cited again].
The market identity transformed managerial
structures and 'has created an enterprise,
competitive culture'. It did not affect the
curriculum so much, but did introduce 'new
discourses of management and economy', say in the
training of school head teachers. In other
words, it has 'radically transformed the
regulative discourse of the institution'.
External competitive demands are stronger.
This position has been supported by the
state. However, contradictions with the more
traditional curriculum and the identities it
produces have produced 'a new pathological
position at work in education: the pedagogic
schizoid position'[nice, but it could just be a
hybrid, showing the weakness of the original
divisions?]. [Why didn't Maton use this term in
his piece on
cultural studies? Bernstein hints at
instrumentalism reconciling or replacing the two
in the generic mode in the chapter above]
Social change has been described in various ways,
including postmodernism and disembedding, but we
can use the old terms and compare ascribed with
achieved identities. The former have been
now considerably weakened, since the classic
'cultural punctuations and specialisation' (72) of
'age, gender, and age relation'[not ethnicity?]
have been weakened as bases for identity, in
favour of individual achievements. The
dimensions of the life space have also contracted,
reducing age differences. Those identities
achieved through class and occupation have also
become weaker resources, even though equal
distributions remain. Geographic movements
of population also create new sets of cultural
pressures. Overall, there has been a
'disturbance and disembedding of identities'.
The new ones have not just replaced the old ones,
but there are emerging identities - again these
will be considered as decentred, retrospective,
and prospective. The first one relates to
local resources oriented to the present, the
middle one to the effects of 'grand past
narratives', the third one to provide a new
recentred identity for the new conditions,
sometimes based on selections from the past.
Decentred identities produce two
types. The first one is instrumental, where
identities 'are constructed out of market
signifiers'(73) as in consumerism. These can
be coherent, but are not stable over time.
The politics associated with them is anti
centralist. The second one is therapeutic,
relying on internal local resources, introjection,
based on the self as a personal project,
relatively independent of consumerism. 'It
is a truly symbolic construction', with an open
narrative, partly oppositional. Internal
sense making is stressed. Both of these
identities are segmented, but the first one is
segmented by the market, the second by some notion
of personal development. Both are
fragile. In the face of breakdown, the
instrumental can shift to the retrospective
nationalist, and the therapeutic to prospective,
but age and context will be important.
Retrospective identities draw on narratives
of the past for exemplars. Again there are
two types. The fundamentalist, which has
subsets of its own (religious or nationalist)
assumes a stable impervious collective identity,
sometimes with 'a strong insulation between the
sacred and profane', with suspicions of the
corrupt influences of the profane, as in Islamic
fundamentalism, or earlier Jewish orthodoxy.
These identities find it difficult to be
reproduced in the next generation. Age might
have an influence, with the young being drawn to
the emotional, intense 'interactive
participation'(75). The revival of student
fraternities in Europe might also provides an
example. However, social change may weaken
the social basis and produce differences among the
young. The elitist retrospective identity is
based on access to high culture, offering 'an
amalgam of knowledge, sensitivities, manners, of
education and upbringing'[similar to
Bourdieu]. Education and social networks can
overcome upbringing. There are strong
classifications and internal hierarchies, but an
avoidance of the market 'unlike
fundamentalists'[really?]. There is little
emphasis on conversion, unlike fundamentalism,
since what is required is 'the very long and
arduous apprenticeship'. There is less
evidence of 'intense solidarities'- and signs of
narcissism rather than the superego formations of
fundamentalism.
When it comes to prospective identities,
narrative resources are important as well, but
these are 'narratives of becoming' (76), becoming
a social category such as 'race, gender or
region'[all involve imaginary communities?]. These
are individualised, but offer a new basis for
social relations, 'a recentring'. They are
often 'launched' by social movements are initially
evangelist and confrontational, but also have
'strong schismatic tendencies'. They are
also focused on the self. They attempt to desocialise
themselves from earlier identities, and depend on
new group supports for a new forms of economic and
political activity. Apparently, 'in the USA,
Islamic movements have created a new basis for
black identity' leading to new politics and to
entrepreneurialism. The becoming can involve
a recovery of something which is still potential,
but this is productive of heresy and schism, so
'gatekeepers and licencers' become crucial, and
there is a constant struggle over 'the
construction of authentic becoming'.
This identity in particular shows the potential
for 'change in the moral imagination' (77).
Enlightenment announced universal rights, but the
subject became anonymous in the subsequent
universalism. Modern moral imagination may
be offering the reverse, and thus shrinking, with
'empathy and sympathy… only… offered
and received by those who are so licensed'.
However, the subject is no longer anonymous.
To take a homely example, people who are
moderately short may experience themselves as
having a spoiled identity and attempt to
rediscover an authentic voice based on 'valid
scholarship and research', but requiring a
licensed member of the group as a spokesman.
The new social category can be established, but it
is subject to being undermined by 'a more radical
agenda', formulated by those who are excessively
short. This is 'the first schism and a new
shrinking of the moral imagination'. [The
endless procession of the oppressed as Maton puts it]
Overall, we are experiencing 'the weakening of,
and a change of place, of the sacred'. It is
no longer central to the collective social base of
society supported by overlapping institutions like
state, or religion and education. Today, the
basis been weakened and 'the sacred now reveals
itself in dispersed sites, movement and
discourses' in segmented and specialized
forms. Instead of talking of cultural
fragmentation, however, we can see the diverse
local identities as an attempt to pursue these new
forms of solidarity through the 'rituals of
inwardness' [an exact parallel to the
secularisation debate]. Instrumentalism is
the exception. This will deepen pedagogic
schizophrenia, since there has now emerged 'for
the first time a virtually secular, market driven
official pedagogic discourse, practice and
context, but at the same time, there is a revival
of forms of the sacred external to it' (78).
This reverses Durkheim's notion of the sites of
the sacred and profane, and also challenges Weber
on increasing rationalisation, and produces new
tensions between pedagogic identity with their
associated transmission and acquisition, and local
identities. Of course, not all of these new
local identities 'are to be welcomed, sponsored or
legitimated'.
Notes include a definition of pedagogy as 'the
sustained process whereby somebody(s) acquires new
forms or develops existing forms of conduct,
knowledge, practice and criteria from somebody(s)
or something deemed to be an appropriate provider
and evaluator... We can distinguish between:
institutional pedagogy and segmented (informal)
pedagogy'. Informal pedagogy is carried out
in every day experience by informal providers, it
may be tacit or explicit, and the producer may or
may not be aware that the transmission is taken
place. Informal pedagogy ease tend to be
limited to the context or segment, producing
'unrelated competencies'. There is an
interaction between informal and explicit forms,
governed by framing regulations which produce
varieties of voice and message '(what is made
manifest, what can be realized)' (79).
Sometimes, the acquirer can initiate change in
these. Overall identity 'is the outcome of
the "voice message" relations'.
|
|