Notes on: Cantu, E. & Jussim, L (2022).
Microaggressions, Questionable Science, and Free
Speech. Texas Review of Law and Politics,
26:218 – 267
https://sites.rutgers.edu/lee-jussim/wp-content/uploads/sites/135/2021/02/microaggressions-and-law-submitted.pdf
[NB I got both the offprint and the web version
--page numbers refer to the offprint]
Dave Harris
This is a popular topic, and diversity
administrators often include lists claiming that
racism is often unconscious. Legal academics are
even using microaggressions research in proposing
legal change. This article questions the
scientific legitimacy about the claims made by
psychologists — one author is a psychologist.
Instead, 'ideological glue' is responsible for the
'propagative success' of the term and it risks
'socially caustic and legally pernicious effects'
unless treated with scepticism.
One of the authors was asked by his institution to
complete a training programme featuring
unconscious bias and microaggressions. He was
presented with a list of statements and questions
that apparently constitute microaggressions, and
they included questions like whether he had 'made
the statement "I don't see colour"… Complained
that someone or something is too "PC"; or "asked a
person of colour to explain something about their
culture"' (219). An affirmative answer would
amount to an admission 'of having expressed at
least unconscious racism'.
Microaggresions are acts 'often facially
innocuous' [I think this means on the face of it]
'that conveys subtle animus or bias against
someone in a traditionally marginalised group'.
They are going to look only at spoken
microaggressions and racial bias. Combating them
is an attempt to root out the most insidious forms
of racism, the subtlest forms such as language,
habits that reinforce racial stereotypes. They are
increasingly the focus of social justice
discourse, legal scholarship and 'administrative
programming'. They are also 'increasingly the
basis for charges against professors and others
who, for example correct student spelling and
grammar in grading papers'. At 'Emory University,
students have formally demanded that student
evaluation forms include fields wherein students
can report microaggressions committed by
professors' (220).
There is published scholarship on this phenomenon,
but how sound is it? They want to investigate the
'"current microaggression construct" (CMC)', the
current definition and the set of claims
researchers make about it. Legal scholarship has
been enriched by interdisciplinary work, but there
are risks in that sometimes constructs are
accepted as valid without checking the evidence,
in this case provided by psychologists. Sometimes
the concept is useful ideologically, and
'confirmation bias cancels vigilance' (221).
Sometimes people assume that peer-reviewed
publication means 'the idea has by definition been
thoroughly vetted scientifically', even though
psychologists have long canonised claims that
turned out to be false, especially indicated
byp=-;p-p the replication crisis.
In this case, the claim made for legitimacy of CMC
'is significantly unwarranted (222) and its
utility 'limited' it is likely to be 'socially
caustic — and therefore counter-productive in the
quest for social justice'. They doubt that the
commonly propagated lists of microaggressions do
not reflect anything meaningful and remain to be
empirically justified, partly because it is
contaminated by '"methodological activism"'.
The term microaggression was first coined by
Peirce in 1970 in the context of black and white
racial interactions. He mentioned '"white putdowns
done in an automatic, pre-conscious or unconscious
fashion"' (2 to 3). The term existed before then
but as a 'relatively narrow set of acts'. Peirce's
examples included white men saying to black men
'"we are good to you blacks"' which according to
him meant '"we are good to you blacks and you
should be grateful that we control you as gingerly
[sic] and humanely as we do"'. In 2022, Solzarno
et al. gave an example: '"when I talk about those
blacks I really wasn't talking about you", and "if
only there were more of them like you"'.
The concept entered the mainstream through the
work of Sue, who significantly broadened the
construct. He defined racial microaggressions as
'"brief and commonplace daily verbal, behavioural
and environmental indignities, whether intentional
or unintentional, that communicate hostile,
derogatory or negative racial slights and insults
to the target person or group'. These are
continuing and cumulative. Examples include
'"America is a melting pot" which contains an
'embedded meaning that a white speaker "does not
want to acknowledge race" and that minorities
should "assimilate" and "acculturate to the
dominant culture"' (224).
Some reactions were critical, but mostly the
article generated lots of research leading to the
CMC, and lots of similar definitions, such as
Williams: '"deniable [extra] acts of racism that
reinforce pathological stereotypes and inequitable
social norms"'. They have 'a list of
microaggressions taken from diversity training
materials and a major US university in the
appendix'. It includes: '"you're a credit to your
race"… (Rough translation: "your race is
unimpressive but you're one of the few good
ones")', which they take to be 'reasonably deemed
as likely rooted in racism', but other items are
more problematic, much broader and lacking an
adequate basis. Psychologists have provided no
valid basis, although the CMC looks as if it is
the product of rigourous science. It does have the
effect of stigmatising and silencing those who do
not share the ideological assumptions of the
microaggression researchers.
Accepting the commonly propagated list has 'little
to no basis'. Other psychologists have said this
to, and identified numerous weaknesses including
that '"there is no research evidence that the
microaggressions identified… are linked either
probabilistically or inexorably to the negative
messages" researchers claim are embedded in
them'(225 – 6). That is because researchers are
ascribing racist meaning to often innocuous acts
and language, and doing so for metaphysical
reasons.
They are insisting that microaggressive items
'have intrinsically embedded racist meanings'
regardless of the non-racist intent of the speaker
or even the 'lack of malign interpretation by the
recipient' (226). They have been able to 'divine
objectively racist meanings in facially innocuous
acts that others cannot detect'. The public just
have to believe they can do this, to 'discern
hidden forces and essences in social phenomena'.
This is 'now common in social justice discourse
and critical academic theory'. Williams, for
example has argued that a statement like '"America
is a melting pot"' is a microaggression, but this
is not based on the conscious intent of the
offender or the perception of the target – instead
it is '"by nature offensive… a form of racism"'
(227). Acts can be 'inherently and at least
unconsciously racist' because 'by definition
[they] are caused by socially conditioned racial
biases and prejudices… designed to reinforce the
traditional power differentials between groups,
whether or not this was the conscious intention of
the offender'. [Clear hints of false consciousness
here, some world historic role for white people]
Speakers are at least negligent in directing some
packet of 'objectively extent coded racism'
towards a recipient. Such acts must be rooted in
racist beliefs, some hidden meta communication,
for Sue, beneath the level of awareness. The logic
seems to be that you define a situation where A
causes B, then if you establish that A has caused
B you know you have that situation: to conclude an
act as a microaggression, you have to demonstrate
that it has been caused by racism, but how do you
show that there are racist messages embedded in
microaggressions, including questions such as
'"can I touch your hair?" Or '"how did you get so
good at science?"'. For microaggression
researchers, there is an alleged embedded meaning
in these questions, but it seems at least as
plausible that the speakers believe something
else, that partners are good at science [or have
touchable hair], and this is equally plausible as
a 'default embedded meaning'. Why should a racist
embedded meaning be more likely '"by nature"', as
Williams argues?. She just rejects the possibility
of alternatives, but provides no meaningful
evidence to support the claim.
It might be possible to get evidence. They could
assess levels of racism among a group of whites
independently, and then see if there is a
correlation with the likelihood of committing
microaggressions, and then rule out alternative
explanations. However this is not been done so
far. Instead researchers have simply assumed there
are embedded meanings and declared statements and
questions to be microaggressions 'essentially by
fiat' (229). They have relied on 'intuitive
assumptions' as a basis of their methodology.
Sue et al. in the original 2007 article offered a
list of microaggressions that has subsequently
been highly influential in the preparation of
various lists, although the authors themselves
only said that these items '"may potentially be
classified as racial microaggressions"'. As a
critic said, this 'taxonomy… was generated in an
armchair fashion"' although it has subsequently
been used as a template.
Focus group methodology has been used
subsequently, where POC participants were put into
small discussion groups to discuss
microaggressions they think they suffered and new
items were generated. Here participants'
intuitions replace those of researchers, but it is
still 'subjective self reporting', and this is
still 'clearly insufficient for showing that
listed microaggressive items have objectively
embedded in them racist messages. The subjects
might also have been highly selected and '"already
predisposed to endorse the concept"' and POC
might suspect subtle racism is at play.
The same goes with appeals to lived experience, as
Williams has offered, apparently replacing the
need to prove any connections. However, 'academics
can claim anything they like about their lived
experience, which is why such experiences do not
count as scientific evidence' (230).
So the methodology involves simply asking POC or
other psychologists to think of ways in which
racism can manifest itself in language, and
thinking of examples that they 'intuitively
conclude' reflect subtle racism. What makes it
correct? For Williams, the whole complaint
is a red herring, and the issue is whether the
behaviour reinforces pathological stereotypes and
promotes exclusion, and whether it is also easy to
explain away as nothing to do with race [I think].
This is still unsatisfactory, because the original
emphasis was on unconscious intents rather than
explicit behaviour, and it is not so clear what
rationalising away might look like if the emphasis
is on effects anyway [I think]: Williams seems to
be now focusing on effects not on states of mind.
It also asks for a difficult test, whether or not
pathological stereotypes are actually reinforced
as a necessary effect. In practice, Williams is
probably just claiming that she should be believed
because she is an expert. There is also an
incoherence in seeing rationalisation involving
nonracial factors as really evidence of racial
intents, making 'the breadth of acts qualifying as
microaggressions… breathtakingly vast and
indeterminate' (232).
So there is still no consistent substantiation and
proper evidence. Can the methodology be
reconstructed? Perhaps you should focus on POC
experience of microaggressive acts, if they are
authoritative and accurately record objective
embedded meanings of facially innocuous language,
as microaggressions scholars claim. Apparently,
53% of black participants in a study believed the
question about being good at science was 'at least
"slightly racist" in context' [1 of the
researchers was Williams]. Surely this is
'extremely weak evidence of racist embedded
meanings'? Williams speculates that the remaining
47% were either less intelligent or engaging in
denial, or perhaps simply not offended by
anything, anything rather than they correctly
perceive the question as not a microaggression.
What does the finding of 53% saying it was
slightly racist actually mean — that hardly anyone
who says this is racist, or everyone who says this
is a tiny bit racist? The responses are not broken
down into proportions of slightly racist or very
racist anyway, but are presented as 'at least
slightly racist'. Similar problems affect many of
the other items in the study. 'There have been no
rigourous preregistered attempts to replicate the
study' and there is a long history of dismal
replication rates anyway. The study was conducted
'with a small sample of 20 black students' and
focused on college-age students in one region of
the USA, who had probably been already exposed to
diversity training, so they were probably already
primed to agree with the researchers. No other
study they have found does any better in
demonstrating 'that POC agree with researchers
about what constitutes microaggressions' nor that
there is any consistent agreement about the common
lists of microaggressions (236).
What about measuring the racism of white people to
see if they commit listed micro-aggressive acts?
Williams invokes a study by Kanter and Williams
and says it provides empirical support that
microaggressive acts are rooted in racist beliefs
and feelings. They first asked black participants
to review various microaggressions to see if they
believe they were at least possibly racist. They
could score the items as somewhat racist or very
racist. They chose the items that at least half of
them saw as possibly racist. They then asked white
participants to review the other items and rank
how likely they were to say or think them. Then
they measured the racial hostility of the white
participants. Again this was only a small scale
study, 33 black and 118 whites, all from one
university. No replication again. It established
correlations. Even so, only 10 of 30
correlations reached the conventional cut-off for
significance; for two thirds of the supposed
microaggressions there was no meaningful
relationship between white prejudice and the
likelihood of expressing it. Among the two thirds
of microaggressions that failed to meaningfully
correlate with white racism 'most were the very
ambiguous items that give rise to overbreadth
challenges to the CMC. In other words the facially
innocuous items that researchers claim are
microaggressions — the only items that make the
CMC allegedly useful — the very items the
researchers failed to connect with white racism'
(237). One microaggression — 'I "don't think of
black people as black"' correlated with positive
attitudes toward blacks!
Even if all the correlations were significant, all
that we would learn is that 'the more racist
someone is the more likely they are to do or say
things that POC deemed problematic'. We would not
be able to conclude that microaggressive items are
'"rooted in" racism' (238) any more that we could
argue that carrying a pocketknife is rooted in
violent tendencies just because those who carry
them more likely to commit acts of violence.
Detailed examination of the microaggression items
reveals further problems. One item that at least
half of the black participants found to be '"at
least possibly racist" concerns a statement where
a white person with a mixed group of friends is
talking about current events including police
brutality and says that he doesn't think of black
people as black, that he is colourblind, which
comes over as a microaggression that suggests that
he is not recognising '"identity-based
experiences, challenges and needs"'. 33.3% of
black participants saw this item as possibly
racist, 27.3% somewhat or very racist. Possibly
racist is a very low threshold, but that was the
response for the majority of items, and only 13 of
them 'were identified by a majority of the black
participants as "somewhat" or "very" racist':
merging the data gives a misleading impression.
The more obviously offensive statements were the
ones that were deemed somewhat or very racist like
'"you are smart for a black guy"'. Asking to touch
hair directed at a black woman was found to be
racist by only 27.3 of black students — most of
them, apparently saw this as 'likely simply a
genuine expression of appreciation of difference
or otherwise nonracist, even if sometimes annoying
to black women' (240). Including clearly racist
items with ambiguous ones gives the impression
that they all belong on the same continuum and
again there is no basis for this. There is an
assumption that everyone agrees these are racist
acts. The same goes with the exercise correlating
matters with white racism. Again the statement
about being smart for a black guy does correlate
with negative attitudes towards black people, but
Williams makes the assumption that the correlation
of the total scale is some sort of evidence that
all the listed items are microaggressions,
including the ambiguous and apparently nonracist
items which 'ride on the correlative coat tails of
the more blatant' (241).
Methods like this appear central in maintaining
the legitimacy of CMC. Otherwise surveys like this
would merely proclaim the banal — that pretty
blatant statements can be microaggressions.
Instead they want to claim that all 30 questions,
including innocuous ones, are rooted in racism,
validating the whole list.
However, neither of these further experiments,
correlating either with recipient perceptions or
white racists, is commonly cited, because neither
is likely to strongly justify the researchers'
claims, especially about hidden meta
communications. There are no robust tests:
'researchers conclusions about embedded meanings
appears to be a priority belief in the existence
of those embedded meanings' (241). We can
represent 'the current propagative success of the
CMC [as] an example of "idea laundering"' (242).
In idea laundering, peer review gets captured by
activists so that 'certain idea logically and
rhetorically useful claims have scientific
credibility'. Once an article is published it can
be cited by other articles as evidence for the
validity of a claim. CMC is just such a product,
growing in the psychological scholarship and
broader culture, hard to resist unless you're
prepared to dive into primary sources. Kanter has
shown that strongly bigoted statements do reflect
prejudice against 118 students and 33 black ones,
and this study is now cited as evidence
'"indicative of racial prejudice and offenders"'
(243). [ie on another sample?] We want more
severe testing, ideally seeking alternative
explanations and additional research.
Ideally this would be aimed at finding new
manifestations of microaggressions, and
replicating the existing work with larger samples
and meta-analytic studies. Preregistered work
would be needed to reduce researcher biases — the
'hypotheses, methods and analyses would all need
to be articulated in writing prior to conducting
the study'. The work is still by these standards
in its infancy, 'most definitely not ready for
real-world application'.
There are other problems as well, turning, for
example on the constancy of microaggression,
daily, according to Sue. This has been tested, and
one study found that POC had not experienced
microaggression 'in the past six months at all, or
if they had, did so 1 to 3 times' (244). It's hard
to see this as constituting a major social problem
or having a terrible caustic effect.
Overall, it's hard to see CMC as representing
scientific activity at all, but rather as 'an
activism', where widespread and subtle racism is
assumed and activist narrative is the preordained
conclusion. This overcomes the problem that CMC is
listing items that people do or say that could be
inspired by racism. Instead it claims to have
revealed something hitherto invisible,
groundbreaking and important, something insidious,
and therefore compatible with CRT.
CRT is social constructionist, focusing on
'"demeaning patterns of thought and speech"'
(246), with inequality persisting because of
'something secret, subtle, hidden and
underground'. Initially there were concepts such
as 'symbolic racism'or 'implicit bias', with each
greeted by initial enthusiasm and publication,
followed by critical review highlighting
weaknesses and alternative explanations.
Microaggression is now invaluable to CRT,
especially the argument that overt racism has
transformed into subtle racism, as a tactic
designed to preserve white supremacy, a new social
mechanism, identifiable only by critical minds.
Microaggression research provides 'a veneer of
scientific credibility' to these critical premises
with all its paraphernalia of statistics and
reliability coefficients [odd, because another
tradition criticises positivism, of course].
However, because of methodological shortcomings,
significant assumptions and 'the tactic of concept
creep' (248) are also essential.
Take the idea that the racism in microaggression
is unconscious, that there must be intent even
though it does not appear in individual
consciousness, that there is intentionality in
fact, appearing as a manifestation of the goals of
the group. There is this idea of 'society's
intent' — 'a creature of critical social
metaphysics' (249). At the same time there is
'methodological activism', advancing CRT,
criticising scientific method as an illegitimate
constraint on ways of knowing by traditionally
marginalised people, hence emphasising the
experience of some POC, rejecting too much
empiricism as imperialism. Sue rejects evidence as
representing dominant values, especially
scientific scepticism, with his critics imposing
their own racial realities, 'made in the
unmistakable spirit of post-modernism' (250) that
scientific rigour is really a powerplay. Williams
has the same response to her critics, identifying
a '"racist framework"' (251) in one demand for
empirical substantiation, and seeing such a demand
itself as a aggression, demanding a review from a
diversity researcher, reinforcing pathological
stereotypes for denouncing Williams as being angry
and aggressive. All this shows 'an aggressive
fragility, combined with an assumed but
unjustified moral and epistemic authority' that
sees challenges to CMC as racists or racially
insensitive, this is really 'powerplay' (252).
What do CRT and CMC advocates actually propose?
They want to change society for the better, but
they also seem to want to 'stigmatise and silence
those who disagree with a certain ideological view
of social reality', including those who challenge
their work. Microaggression has 'insinuative
power', connoting hostility, oppression,
domination, an example of 'tactical concept
creep'. This phenomenon has accompanied psychology
becoming a '"tribal moral community" bound
together by moral commitments to social justice
and progressive ideals"' (253), with victim
groups: the concept of harm has crept, together
with concepts like abuse and discrimination, so
that it is '"ever harder for anyone to defend
themselves against ugly moral charges"'.
Microaggression researchers are able to declare to
be microaggressions any statement that reflect
reasonable disagreements. Williams has said that
if a white person says to a black person that they
just don't believe in political correctness but
that does not mean they are racist this amounts to
a microaggression, a denial of individual racism,
not just a lack of self-awareness or simple
mindedness. Any white person who denies that they
are racist or who dislikes political correctness
'is a racist because of that denial' (254'. It is
also a racist microaggression for a white person
to oppose affirmative action by seeing it as
conveying unfair advantages. The same goes for
colour blindness, or saying there is only one
race, which do not celebrate diversity or
emphasise common humanity, but brand people as
racists including those who 'may have constructive
doubts about the legitimacy of "identity
politics"' (255). CMC is a device for
weaponisation against those with more conservative
or liberal views.
Sue thinks a racist microaggression is the
statement that the most qualified person should
get the job, because it reflects the myth of
meritocracy. CRT theorists used to think that
meritocrats were naïve or uninformed, but 'CMC
posits that they are racists'. This might stifle
debate about who to appoint as the best candidate
if the main issue is to avoid microaggression.
Overall, CMC has insulated itself from healthy
challenge. Interlocutors have been stigmatised and
silenced. [It is incorrigible internally]. It is
'little more than a mechanism to vindicate the
intuitive hunches of those who see racism as more
pervasive than others do' (256).
There are costs, harms. Both authors have come
from 'traditionally marginalised groups' but
neither remembers being assaulted with
microaggressions, nor experiencing extreme harm.
They don't conclude that subtle racism is as
widespread as CRT thinks. Yet POC are being taught
that they are under constant assault, that they
'are being conditioned to be constructively
offended… In situations that do not implicate
racism… Being encouraged to develop what Sue et
al. term a "healthy paranoia"' (258). Racial
paranoia is not healthy. White people may be being
taught that racism permeates everything they do
and that they should 'walk on egg shells when
interacting with POC'. There may be a chilling
effect on free speech.
Walking on egg shells can also be considered a
racist microaggression, of course — '"aversive
racism"' for Williams — exclusion and
ostracisation as forms of aggression, avoidance,
even well-intentioned. Denial of committing
microaggression is a microaggression and can be
the same as gas lighting. The overall effect can
be 'the most significant prerequisites to reducing
bigotry: interpersonal connection, goodwill,
interpretive charity, and a reflexive humanism'
(259).
The Supreme Court is not likely to ban speech
claimed to be microaggressions, but there is a
worry about campus speech codes. Many colleges
have '"bias reporting systems"' where people are
encouraged to report anything they witness.
Universities often push or even violate First
Amendment boundaries [microaggressive speech
cannot be banned under the First Amendment] to
protect students from offensive speech. Academic
culture is already inclined to subscribe to ideas
like CMC. One professor was fired for criticising
the concept of microaggressions and failing to
attend microaggression training. Student
protesters at UCLA have attacked professors for
correcting students' grammar. The University was
advised to police microaggression in order to
dilute conduct like this in the future, and, at
Emory University, student evaluation is likely to
be used to punish professors even if they 'had no
way of knowing [they] would be perceived as
racist' (261).
Microaggression is so subjective and elastic that
an objective definition is '"all but impossible in
practice"'. There is unlikely to be a shared
understanding. Reports may infringe the First
Amendment, but there is '"an invisible line, drawn
by known only to the offended party"' [at least
you have a First Amendment in the USA]. Informal
punishments like those at Emory come very close to
pressuring professors to toe the line. Ithaca
College came close to developing an online
reporting system so that '"oppressors"' would have
their name recorded. Even Sue has been worried
about the implications.
Delgado has called for regulation for the '"subtle
nuances and codewords"', including '"body
language"' (262), and has suggested that the First
Amendment courts are pressured to accommodate
campus speech codes, and this has been echoed by
people like Matsuda and others. CRT is gaining
ground. The post-modern argument that discourse
shapes reality and identity is as well, and social
sciences are increasingly claiming to uncover
subtle aspects of daily life such as discourse
norms and their role in power. The whole thing
will end in 'increasing demands for the policing
of ever more subtle aspects of human interaction',
(264) beginning with college campuses.
They think that they are only scratching the
surface of the problem by focusing on definition.
A 'broad and indeterminate number of acts' have
been declared as 'inherently subtly racist' and 'a
number of those in positions of power have been
ideological inclined' to adopt them. In practice,
CMC does little more than 'retroactively validate
initial ideological hunches', and 'at best, to
give voice to POC by substituting the scientific
method for the perceptions of some of them'.
Nobody should take the current lists as
representative of anything meaningful.
 | |